Though St. Thomas Aquinas is by far
the most famous Christian Aristotelian, he was by no means the only one as
there were also many others such as Marsilius of Padua, whose essay in History of Political Philosophy was
written by Leo Strauss. Though they were both Christians and heavily influenced
by Aristotle, it is not the case that Aquinas had a major impact on Marsilius’
thought as Marsilius only references Aquinas once in his Defender of the Peace. So as he was a Christian and a Aristotelian,
but not a Thomist, Marsilius ended up coming to a far different conception of
the proper Christian application of Aristotle’s philosophy than Aquinas did.
For one thing, while Marsilius accepts the idea of the priesthood being
divinely established, and separated from the rest of the believers, he denies
that the Church hierarchy is. Thus, for Marsilius, the priesthood must be seen
as equal. He also takes any other ideas more directly from Aristotle, as he
sees the purpose of what he calls the “commonwealth” which is roughly equal to
the Aristotelian conception of the City, as being to enable me to live the good
life. Furthermore, Marsilius also sees the commonwealth as the grounding for
other kinds of causes. This is not to say that Marsilius was simply
regurgitating Aristotle, as he did have some major disagreements with him. The
biggest and most obvious of these would be on the Christian revelation for
while Aristotle had no conception of such an idea, Marsilius saw it as being
able to cure the diseases of the commonwealth. Though there was a major
disparity from their teachings, it should be remembered that in Marsilius’
mind, he was not contradicting Aristotle as much as he was bringing up a point
that Aristotle simply overlooked. For Marsilius, Aristotle’s problem was that
as a pagan, he lacked a proper conception of the divine.
Though Marsilius accepts the idea
that the priesthood is to be above the rest of the believers, it should not be
inferred from this that they are to rule over the body of believers, but rather
should act more like teachers or judges. Hos the commonwealth is to be ruled
though is important as Marsilius is highly focused on the unity of the
commonwealth, as for him unity is the very thing the disease of the
commonwealth seeks to destroy, which will then bring about anarchy and thereby
harm the good life. This fear of anarchy Marsilius has is important as for him
any regime, even an unjust regime is still ultimately better than no regime.
This sort of notion ultimately leads to Marsilius being more concerned with
mere law than the best law and mere government than the best government.
Despite this fear of no government, Marsilius displays a surprisingly
democratic streak for a man of his time as he sees political authority as
ultimately relying upon the whole of the body of citizens, what he calls the
Human Legislator. Perhaps not surprisingly considering his admiration of
Aristotle and his democratic streak, Marsilius sees Aristotle as being far more
democratic than he is typically seen as being.
So powerful is the Human Legislator
for Marsilius, it has the power to elect and dispose of priests, thus reversing
the traditional distinction between the people and the priests in favor of the
people. In order to justify such a radical move towards democracy, Marsilius
gives four proofs in order to justify placing so much power in the hands of the
Human Legislator. Ultimately though, his fourth proof is just a summation of
the first three, so only the first three proofs will be mentioned here. They
are as follows: 1) Legislative power ought from those whom the best human laws
can emerge, and as no man would willingly vote to do harm to himself, the Human
Legislator will be able to produce the best laws. 2) Each man will be able to
assure the laws are observed. 3) Each man will be able to better know what
benefits or harms each. Though the Human Legislator is to rule the
commonwealth, and while it is to be made up of the entire body of the citizens,
it is not an egalitarian program as those that are to rule the Human Legislator
are its most able part. Though doing this, Marsilius has, in a way, produced a
synthesis between oligarchy and democracy. By creating his divide between the
Human Legislator and the most able members of the Human Legislator, Marsilius
returns to Aristotle’s view that the Human Legislator (the sovereign) is
identical with the ruling part (the government). Furthermore, Marsilius also
sees the ruler as part of the legislator.
Marsilius’ conception of law,
order, and government ultimately leads him to the conclusion that the supremacy
of the law is not absolute as it may be necessary to act illegally in order to
save the commonwealth. Still, he still displays a surprising commitment to
democracy, at least in its majoritarian form, for a man of his day as he draws
a parallel between the “the whole body of the citizens” of his Human Legislator
to “The Whole Body of the Faithful” of the New Testament, thus giving his
radical new system a Christian justification. Marsilius also takes his
dedication of democracy all the way to the monarchy as while he favors
monarchy, he untimely wants for it to be an elected monarchy. It may be
surprising to some to hear that he ultimately favored monarchy, considering how
radical his commitment to democracy is elsewhere. Marsilius ultimately does
have justification for this as he believes that above all else the king/ ruler
must have prudence, and therefor needs whatever system allows him to have the
most prudence. For Marsilius, this system was most likely elective monarchy.
Still though, Marsilius keeps the idea that unity is essential for a
commonwealth, but contra many others, he does not think the rule of many will
harm the unity of the commonwealth. In fact, for Marsilius the rule of many is
the best way to bring about unity as the Human Legislator can more easily
produce laws that people are likely to obey. In a way then, Marsilius here
produces a synthesis between populism and absolute monarchy.
Marsilius, to be sure still sees
the priesthood as being highly important, but ultimately he does not want them
to rule as he sees the spirit of the priesthood as being incompatible with the
qualities that are needed to rule. Such an idea can be seen as being rooted in
the Christian duty to obey as well as the Christian call to poverty. The idea
that the priests are not meant to rule eventually produces some other highly
interesting ideas in Marsilius’ thought. For one, while divine law has no
coercive element in and of itself; human can be coercive in its dealings with
those that violate divine law. Also, Marsilius allows for the Human Legislator
to pass laws enforcing religions orthodoxy as if people were permitted to
disobey divine law, eventually divine law would lose its power. This leads him
to a highly interesting conclusion, particularly for someone that claimed to be
a member of the Roman Catholic Church, as Marsilius sees a universal prince as
being more important than a universal bishop, as a universal prince can make
people keep the faith. Ultimately though, Marsilius sees a universal prince as
being unnecessary. Two more things to keep in mind is that while Marsilius uses
the term “divine law”, divine law should not be equated with natural law as for
Marsilius, there is no such thing as natural law. It should also be kept in
mind that Marsilius can be seen as setting the state for the rise of
Machiavelli, as both saw that there was no enforceable law other than what
humans made.
Perhaps the most obscure philosopher
to be included in History of Political
Philosophy, Leo Strauss does a fine job of shedding light on another
version of Christian Aristotelian philosophy apart from the dominant Thomist
tradition. This essay shows while interpretation is generally considered to be
Strauss’s best quality and is well worth reading for anyone interested in the
thought of Marsilius of Padua. Marsilius, for as obscure as he is personally
serves as a major influence for one of the most important political theorists
to ever live and thus deserves to be studied. This essay will hopefully be able
to encourage further study of Marsilius of Padua’s thought.
No comments:
Post a Comment