Carnes Lord’s entry in Strauss and Cropsey’s History of Political Philosophy, deals
with Aristotle, who along with Socrates and Plato, is the most famous and influential
philosopher of the ancient world, and the man whose writings, when combined
with Christianity, help formulate the foundation for much of Medieval
philosophy, a foundation which is still highly influential on much of the
contemporary Roman Catholic philosophy. Regardless of this, Aristotle is still
to be highly regarded in his own right as he serves as an important expansion
and counter to Plato’s writings on political philosophy as well as contributing
highly important ideas of his own.
One of the most important concepts to understand with
Aristotle is his distinction between the “practical” and “theoretical”
sciences. This distinction is still used today, but Aristotle used it
differently than contemporary scientists and philosophers of science do. In its
modern meaning, “theoretical” science deals with the more obtuse ideas behind
the functioning of science while “practical” science deals with more of its
application to actually existing life. For Aristotle though, the distinction
between these two concepts is that while theoretical science is concerned with
the things that do not change or the things in which the principle of change is
found in the object itself, practical science is concerned with man. From this
distinction, we can have a better grasp on what sort of audience Aristotle is addressing
when he talks about politics. He is not addressing philosophers of even
students of philosophy, but rather political men. Furthermore, Aristotle also
divides political/ practical science into three branches: ethics, economics,
and the science of governing. Of these three, the science of governing most
closely aligns with what is commonly thought of as “political science” today.
One of the major elements of Aristotle’s thought is his idea
of happiness. But while many in the modern era see happiness as subjective, for
Aristotle, happiness was objective and connected to the proper use of an object
in accordance to reason. As a result of this, there is a strong connection
between virtue and happiness in Aristotle’s thought. Virtue though for
Aristotle is neither a part of nor contrary to human nature, but rather formed
by habit. For Aristotle, the way to become a virtuous person is to act in a virtuous
manner. Just as virtue was connected to the proper use of an object and thus
objective, so was justice. Justice in the most general sense is seen as the
disposition to perform acts of virtue in accordance with the laws of the city,
while in the particular sense; justice is seen as disposition to take a fair
share of the good things. Justice can also be seen as the correction of wrongs.
With this conception of justice in mind, we can now make note of two divisions
in political justice Aristotle creates: 1) justice as being what is right by
nature and 2) justice as what is right by law.
Friendship is also an important part of Aristotle’s thought.
While “friendship” for Aristotle does have its modern meaning, it also means
the love between family members and some sense of civic pride/ patriotism. Thus,
friendship becomes an important part of governing. Another significant part of
proper governing is prudence, which Aristotle sees as the virtue proper to the
rational part of the soul and without it, the proper practice of politics is
impossible. This leads to Aristotle’s understanding of the polis. For
Aristotle, the polis is a community, as things are held in common, once again
illustrating that that the state/ society distinction that makes up so much of
modern political theory would be unknown to Aristotle. With that being said, it
should be noted that Aristotle does not take this idea as far as Plato does as
he does recognize other kinds of rule rather than just the political and uses
that recognition to argue against Platonic communism. Still, for Aristotle, man
is a political animal and the city is seen as natural.
While Aristotle does not recognize a distinction between the
polis and society, he does recognize a distinction between the polis and the
regime. He uses the idea of citizenship to further understand this distinction
for while the good man acts virtuous, the good citizen tries to preserve the
political partnership. This distinction, between regime and polis allows
Aristotle to see six different types of regimes that can be grouped into two different
categorical sets. One set deals with how many rulers, while the other set deals
with whether the regime is virtuous or not. The first set can be divided into
three more categories, the rule of one, the rule of few, and the rule of many.
Thus, for each type of rule based on how many rule, there is a virtuous and
non-virtuous version of it. The virtuous version of the rule of one is known as
kingship while the non-virtuous rule of one is known as tyranny. Likewise, the
virtuous rule of few is aristocracy while the non-virtuous rule of few is
oligarchy. Finally, the virtuous rule of many is known as polity while the
non-virtuous rule of many is known as democracy. The many different types of
regimes are a reflection upon the fact that there are many different parts of
the city. One thing that should be noted is that the types of regimes Aristotle
notes should not be thought of as mutually exclusive, as there can be mixed
regimes.
One of the more interesting aspects
of Aristotle’s views on the best way to govern the polis is that he does give
an early example of the importance of the middle class on the stability of the
regime. For Aristotle, regimes need a “middling agent” between the rich and the
poor to help eliminate the tension between them and help bring about stability.
Still, even ignoring his lack of state/ society distinction, Aristotle is not a
simple precursor to modern political theorists noting the importance of the
middle class on a society’s stability as he does consider aristocracy to be the
best regime as it allows the most virtuous men to rise up and rule.
Furthermore, Aristotle is more critical of market-based societies than many
modern political theorists are as he thinks it is better for the rule of the
aristocracy to be based on land rather than trade, and as such the city should
not be a port itself, as such cities become overly reliant on trade. Aristotle
does note though, that the city should be near water.
On a final note, Aristotle also has
an interesting theory regarding the proper place of security in the polis, for
while he does see it as important; he does not see it as paramount. Thus, he
rejects the idea that the best city will be large because large cities can more
easily provide a large military. In response to this claim, Aristotle notes
that while large cities may be able to provide a large military easier than
smaller cities can, it is also more difficult to govern large cities. For
Aristotle, the best way of life is one of virtue, not a focus on security and
as such, the best city should value politics over war.